Proceedings of
the Tenth International Symposium on Theoretical & Applied Linguistics,
April 24-6 1996. Department of Theoretical
and Applied Linguistics, School of English, Aristotle University of
Thessaloniki.
William Labov: A Popperian or not
a Popperian?
PERICLES A. DALTAS
Department of Linguistics,
University of Ioannina.
ABSTRACT
The epistemological criticism of W. Labov's
quantitative paradigm of (socio)linguistic variability has been focused on two issues,
namely, whether or not (a) variable rules are constructed on a
positivist basis, and (b) the inclusion of probabilities in them makes
theoretical sense.
Adopting a popperian outlook, S. Romaine dismisses the
labovian paradigm as positivist on the grounds that Labov has expressed the
view that he feels entitled to consider his model right since he has diligently
tried time and again to prove it wrong but without success. However, this kind of rhetorical outburst on
the part of theoreticians in favour of their beloved models is quite common
(Popper himself does it) and does not in itself jeopardize the theoretical
value of such models; for, their value
crucially depends on their content, that is, on whether they are constructed in
such a way as to facilitate the most detailed criticism possible. Judging by the severe and meticulous
criticism that has been levelled against the quantitative paradigm over the
years, we can safely conclude that this model has been endowed with a high
degree of refutability.
Romaine also considers it unpopperian that probabilities are included in labovian rules of variability on the grounds that no finite number of observations would suffice to prove a probabilistic statement wrong, for which purpose an infinite number of observations would be required. However, Labov's approach to sociolinguistics is commonsense in the popperian sense of the word: it aims at gradually improving, through criticism, both our understanding of the relevant phenomena and the quality of our theoretical tools rather than striving to secure an unshakeable a priori theoretical basis, i.e., before the actual work of sociolinguistic analysis ever begins. In this context, probabilities deriving from observed frequencies have to be taken with a sizeable pinch of salt: they cannot be said to reflect any inherent qualities of the sociolinguistic data since the nature of such qualities is normally beyond the researcher's reach; yet, they serve as statements open to criticism, i.e. they are reproducible and refutable, and, therefore, may lead to better theoretical models.
1. INTRODUCTION
The epistemological criticism of W. Labov's
quantitative paradigm of (socio)linguistic variability focuses on two issues,
namely, (a) whether variable rules are constructed on a
positivist rather than on a Popperian basis, and (b)
whether the inclusion of probabilities in them makes theoretical sense.
2. LABOV, POPPER AND POSITIVISM
Quantitative sociolinguists of the classical Labovian
school of thought have been described as positivist (Romaine 1981) in that they
seem to proceed from inductive observation to the construction of general
models of analysis. To put it in
DeCamp's (1970) apposite terms, such researchers still appear to be in their ΅butterfly
collectionΆ stage.
Sir Karl Popper pointed out the inadequacy of the
positivist paradigm in the 1930's, when he insisted that ¤there is no
induction¥ (1976:86) since all observation takes place in the context of
expressly stated or tacitly accepted theories, or, as he characteristically put
it (1972:71), ¤all knowledge is theory-impregnated, including our
observations¥. Thus, scientific method
does not consist in attempting to corroborate our theories, for no single
observation or test can conclusively prove a general theory right: however many white swans we may spot we can
never safely conclude that All swans are
white, since the possibility of coming across a swan of a different colour
cannot logically be excluded (Popper 1976:43).
On the contrary, scientific progress results from the refutation of our best theories: a single counter-example is enough to
demolish even the best theory, or at least a problematic phenomenon may show a
theory to be of limited applicability and mark the beginning of an attempt to
improve it. As a result, the
corroboration of a theory takes in effect the form of temporarily surviving the
severest possible tests: the best among
a number of alternative theories is the one which up to now has fared better
than the competition in the face of criticism by the scientific community; this, however, does not mean that the theory
is certain to do just as well in the next test, or that there may not arise a
new theory that does even better.
Popper (1976:132) proposes the following tetradic
schema of theory development:
P1 > TT > EE > P2
According to it, an attempt at theory formation always
starts with a problem (P1) for whose solution a tentative theory
(TT) is formulated. The next step is to
subject the theory to critical examination in order to eliminate possible errors
(EE). Finally, the tentative solution to
the initial problem may cause a series of new problems to emerge or lead to the
discovery of previously unidentified ones (P2). This triggers the reapplication of the
schema, not cyclically, for P2 is different from P1, but
spirally: problem-solving has now moved
on to a new level.
The tetradic schema underlies not only scientific
problem-solving but also dealing with problems in our daily lives. For instance, faced with the need for
improved transportation, we built and have since constantly improved the motor
car, but our tentative solution to the original problem creates new problems,
such as congested roads, air pollution or traffic accidents, which require, at
least partly, their own solutions.
The application of the tetradic schema does not
require a conscious or even human subject:
all living organisms go through the same four stages in dealing with
problems posed by the specific environment in which they live. From this point of view, "from the amoeba to
Einstein is just one step" (Popper 1972:246), as the only difference between
the two is that only Einstein is in a position to eliminate his errors
exosomatically, i.e. by criticising one theory after another on paper rather
than having to either evolve biologically or personally suffer the consequences
of his mistakes.
It follows from the Popperian theory of
problem-solving that both the growth of our scientific theories and our
everyday problem-solving necessarily conform to the above tetradic schema,
irrespective of what theoreticians (or ordinary people) think that they are
doing when they identify problems and devise solutions. This means that Labovian sociolinguists may
be as positivist as they like in striving to corroborate rather than refute
their theoretical approach, i.e., by looking not for counter-examples but for
additional examples in support of their theories. This is so because, to begin with, such
theoreticians will readily acknowledge problematic cases that may be pointed
out to them or that they themselves may come across. More importantly though, in the context of
the scientific community their theorising necessarily conforms to the Popperian
tetradic schema since sooner or later it will be subjected to criticism by
other (socio)linguists. Of course, since
it too is necessarily imbued in theory, criticism by peers may take ages to
become available, may concentrate on only certain aspects of the original
theory, or may in other ways prove equally tentative.
The distinction between what a theoretician thinks he
is doing and what he is actually doing does not seem to be fully grasped by
Romaine (1981:108) in her otherwise correct characterisation as positivist of a
statement by Labov (1972:99) that scientific methodology consists in “trying to
prove to yourself that you are wrong. To
be right means that you have finally, abjectly, hopelessly failed to prove
yourself wrong.”
Indeed, from a Popperian point of view Labov should
know that he or anybody else can only temporarily fail to prove his models
wrong: at any particular moment we may
safely assume that our models are already wrong, though we may not be in a
position as yet to demonstrate their falsity (still, that does not mean that we
should make it too easy for critics to demolish our models lest precious
features are lost for ever). However,
despite Labov's (all too human) emotional outburst in favour of his model, what
really matters is (a) the extent to which this model is in a
position to describe aspects of sociolinguistic reality that as yet other
models cannot describe or cannot as well, and
(b) its content.
With respect to (a) above, it seems to me that the
Labovian quantitative paradigm, though less fashionable of late than it used to
be, is still in a unique position to allow us to think of a sociolinguistic
setup in terms of a system of rules.
Furthermore, as I argue elsewhere (Daltas 1996), the paradigm could be
profitably developed to account for the fuzzy edges that such rules exhibit in
actual use, i.e., when handled by members of the community at various degrees
of proficiency or conformity to the norm.
It should also be stressed that, unlike more
qualitative approaches, the Labovian quantitative paradigm allows us to make
objective observations and reach testable conclusions that linguistics cannot
do without. The reason for this is that,
as Labov revealed to us, not only the layman but also the linguist is an
unreliable source of data of even his own mother tongue, let alone the 5,000 or
so languages of the world, as he has no direct or conscious access to large
chunks of linguistic structure. As a
result, methodological expediency obliges him to go through the
inductive-looking stage of ΅butterfly collectionΆ,
i.e., to act as if he were inductively building new general theories or
improving existing ones. Yet, as we saw
above, however objective his observations or testable his conclusions, they are
both necessarily steeped in theory.
We said above that Romaine (1981:108) is justified in
pointing out Labov's un-Popperian belief that he might be right. Indeed, the essence of Popper's teaching is
that we can consider a theory successful only with respect to the past, for it
is always possible to fail the next test that a member of the scientific
community may devise on the basis on new data.
However, Romaine's criticism is of limited value since it is not
addressed to all theoreticians that do not always adhere to the Popperian
principle of refutation, rather than corroboration, as the organon of
theoretical progress.
One important example of this is Popper himself, who in his writings, apart from acknowledging his shortcomings time and again, also expresses his delight at being right on a great number of occasions. Perhaps he is at his most jubilant, and quite rightly so, when he states (Popper 1972:1):
“I think that I have solved a major philosophical problem: the problem of induction.”
at the beginning of his seminal article with the telling (for the purposes of the present argument) title "Conjectural Knowledge: My Solution of the Problem of Induction". The next two periods, which complete the first paragraph of his article, are phrased in the same triumphant, and therefore un-Popperian, certainty:
“(I must have reached the solution in 1927 or thereabouts.) This solution has been extremely fruitful, and it has enabled me to solve a good number of other philosophical problems.”
This brings us to point (b) above, i.e. a theory's content (rather than the love its creator feels for it) as a criterion of evaluation. According to Popper (1976:79, 86), content is directly proportional to a theory's refutability, i.e., its openness to the severest possible criticism:
“Thus the whole problem of scientific method cleared itself up, and with it the problem of scientific progress. Progress consisted in moving towards theories which tell us more and more - theories of ever greater content. But the more a theory says the more it excludes or forbids, and the greater are the opportunities for falsifying it. So a theory with greater content is one which can be more severely tested. [...] scientific progress turned out not to consist in the accumulation of observations but in the overthrow of less good theories and their replacement by better ones, in particular by theories of greater content.” (op.cit.:79)
It would appear therefore that Romaine's criticism
against Labov (which in the interests of fairness should have been addressed to
Popper too) for his positivist belief that he is right is more rhetorical than
anything else. We would have had a point
in considering Labov not to be a Popperian if it could be demonstrated that the
Labovian paradigm is so constructed as to be immune to criticism. Yet, the severe and multi-faceted criticism
levelled against this model over the years by Romaine herself and by numerous
other critics is in fact evidence of its high degree of refutability, and
therefore of its fundamentally Popperian quality (for a review see Ντάλτας 1996).
3. VARIABLE RULES AND PROBABILITIES
Labov has also been criticised for allowing
probabilities to be included in the structural description of his variable
rules. Following Popper's (1972)
critique against probability theory, Romaine (1981) correctly points out that
formulating in probabilistic terms a theoretical statement concerning the
description of a phenomenon severely reduces the degree of refutability of this
statement. This is necessarily so, for
no finite number of observations would suffice to demonstrate the falsity of a
probabilistic statement: for this
purpose an infinite number of observations would be required.
It has also been considered unsound to derive probabilities
from the observed frequencies of a finite language corpus, as these
probabilities are often tacitly taken to be independent from the particular
corpus and as underlying an unlimited number of language corpora with the same
sociolinguistic characteristics. As
Romaine (1981:114) points out, our sociolinguistic behaviour, beyond the
physiology of its phonetic side, does not obey laws, as do natural phenomena, but rules. "Rules may be broken,
but laws are never violated." (op.cit.)
It is therefore epistemologically unwarranted to generalize from
probabilities deriving from observed frequencies of a particular corpus,
however extensive or varied, in order to make predictions concerning other
corpora.
However, there are two kinds of law. There are the laws of nature and there are
the laws of science, the latter being theoretical statements concerning the
former. Scientific laws are formulated
in the context of specific theoretical schools or traditions, and we are simply
hoping that they reflect fairly faithfully the laws of objective reality. This means three things.
To begin with, we simply suppose that natural laws may
not be broken - it is theoretically conceivable that they may or that they may
under certain conditions. Indeed,
according to one interpretation of the facts, the probabilistic character of
the activity of subatomic particles is inherent and does not depend on the
influence of independent variables. If
this interpretation of the behaviour of the natural world is correct (Popper
(1972:285f.f.) for one does not think it is), then the distinction between
natural laws and sociolinguistic rules is not fundamental. This of course does not mean that the
distinction is unimportant, as the intentionality and symbolic character of
human actions interferes with the application of rules but not of laws -
although in the case of organic nature things are not so simple and at least
intentionality cannot be excluded.
Moreover, there is no reason to suppose that the universe, along with
its laws, has stopped evolving, i.e. changing.
Secondly, a scientific law, being a hypothetical
statement concerning a natural phenomenon, may be wrong. In this case, there will be a difference
between, on the one hand, probabilities calculated on the basis of features of
the phenomenon that are taken to be inherent, and on the other, observed
frequencies. Thus, light was supposed to
move in a straight line until Einstein showed that a ray passing by a star
bends as a result of the pull that the star exerts on it.
Third, as a consequence of the above two points,
probabilities of natural phenomena are calculated, as Sterelny (1983:57f.f.)
points out, on the basis of their assumed characteristics and not from
observations of their behaviour: we do
not need to observe the behaviour of a dice to calculate the probability of any
number between one and six coming up in the next x number of throws. The
mathematical calculation will suffice, though an infinite number of
observations will be subsequently required to decide whether the dice is fair
or not. Yet, in sociolinguistics, where
we are normally ignorant of the inherent characteristics of phenomena, deriving
probabilities from observed frequencies, though epistemologically unsound, is
an expedient way of formulating refutable hypotheses.
From the above, it becomes clear that Labov is a
commonsense theoretician in the Popper's (1972:37) sense of the word: according to it the commonsense approach to
science aims at a gradual improvement of our theories through criticism and not
at a priori securing 'certainty'. Labov (1972b:259) believes that there is no
guarantee against error nor need there be any.
In this he is in complete agreement with Popper (op.cit.:41). For this reason, his programmatic aim is not
to secure an unshakeable theoretical basis before he even starts his research,
nor to invent a number of grand theories (according to Popper (1976:62, 71),
trying to be original interferes with our doing our job properly), but to study
language in a more honest and reliable way on a trial and error basis.
To this purpose, that is to achieve a more responsible
kind of research, Labov devises World 3 creatures, i.e. explicitly formulated
hypotheses inhabiting the third Popperian world (World 1 is inhabited by
objects outside us, and World 2 by our psychological states or ideas that have
not been made explicit yet). The
sociolinguistic variables and quantitative rules proposed by Labov and the
other quantitative sociolinguists are creatures of this type: they have been formulated in such a way as to
facilitate rather than obstruct their critical analysis, as is obvious from the
extremely severe criticism that they have actually been subjected to. In the light of criticism, these hypothetical
schemata reveal considerable theoretical weaknesses. Some of them have been eliminated over the
years, others still persist. For
instance, it is far easier to identify phonological or morphological sociolinguistic
variables than syntactic or semantic ones.
Also, not all variables are equally amenable to quantitative analysis as
the frequencies of some are very unequally distributed in the various
environments of the relevant rule (Ντάλτας 1996). On the other hand, we are now much richer in
knowledge than we were thirty years ago with respect to the quantitative
structure of sociolinguistic phenomena.
Also, we are much better equipped to deal with linguistic theories that
are the product of navel-watching rather than of interaction with World 3 sociolinguistic
inhabitants. The fact that criticism has
already drawn the limits of quantitative variationism is evidence of the high
degree of refutability of the theory, and therefore of its Popperian
underpinnings.
REFERENCES
DeCAMP, D. 1970. Is a sociolinguistic theory possible? In J. Alatis (ed.) 1970. Linguistics and the Teaching of Standard English to Speakers of Other Languages and Dialects. Georgetown University Press. Washington D.C.
LABOV,
W. 1972. Some principles of linguistic methodology. Language in Society 1.
LABOV,
W. 1972b. Sociolinguistic Patterns.
Blackwell. Oxford.
DALTAS,
P. 1997. Κοινωνιογλωσσική Μεταβλητότητα: Θεωρητικά
Υποδείγματα και Μεθοδολογία της Έρευνας. Επικαιρότητα. Αθήνα. [Sociolinguistic Variability: Theoretical Models and Research
Methodology]
POPPER,
K.R. 1972. Objective Knowledge: An
Evolutionary Approach. Oxford University Press. London.
POPPER,
K.R. 1976. Unended Quest: An Intellectual
Autobiography. Fontana/Collins. Glasgow.
ROMAINE,
S. 1981. The status of variable rules in sociolinguistic theory. Journal of Linguistics 17.
STERELNY,
K. 1983. Linguistic theory and variable rules. Language &
Communication 3.1.
Δεν υπάρχουν σχόλια:
Δημοσίευση σχολίου